Equality

Equality

Equality Before the Law in the CEDAW

Article 15: of the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (CEDAW) stipulates, in relation to Equality Before the Law, that all countries are required to ensure that women are given equality before the law. In particular, women must have the same legal capacity as men to enter into contracts and to own property, and they must be given equal treatment in the courts. Laws regarding freedom of movement within the country and choice of residence must treat men and women equally.

The Equality of States

Lassa Oppenheim, in the book entitled The Future of International Law, about The Equality of States, wrote in 1921: 28. The proposed constitution, further, makes no inroad at all on the equality of states. This equality is the indispensable foundation of international society. The idea of equality merely expresses the fact that in all resolutions of the international society every state, whatever may be its size and political importance, obtains one voice and no more than one, that every state can be bound by a resolution only with its consent, and that no state can exercise jurisdiction over another state. It does not and cannot express more.

In no circumstances is it to be asserted that unanimity is a condition for all resolutions of the Conferences, and that all resolutions are void to which one or more states refuse their consent. Of course, such resolutions bind those only who assent to them, and of course unanimous resolutions alone can be considered to be universally binding. But nothing should hinder the Conferences–and so it happened in the two first Conferences–from passing majority resolutions. It must never be lost sight of that such majority resolutions do not go to form a universal but only a general law of nations. Only he who repudiates the necessary distinction between a particular and a general and a universal law of nations can demand unanimity. Now the development which up to the present has taken place in the law of nations has shown the necessity of this distinction.

It would be extremely difficult to enumerate any large number of universally accepted rules of the law of nations–apart from those which have obtained recognition as customary law. We have only to think of the Declaration of Paris, to which some states still refuse assent. History also teaches us that the general law of nations has a tendency gradually to become the universal law of nations. It is therefore permissible, when a forward step which fails to gain unanimous approval has become a practical matter, for that majority of states which is ready for it to take the step by themselves; the dissenting states will give in their adhesion in course of time. And if and when this should turn out not to be the case, such a majority resolution would anyhow represent, in a narrower circle of international society, a step forward from which there is no obligation to forbear merely because others are unwilling to join in taking it.

Does the Constitution of the International Prize Court Violate the Principle of the Equality of States?

Lassa Oppenheim, in the book entitled The Future of International Law, about Does the Constitution of the International Prize Court Violate the Principle of the Equality of States?, wrote in 1921: 53. It is alleged that the principle of equality is violated in that the Prize Court is contemplated as consisting of fifteen members, so that, while the eight Great Powers are always represented by a member, the thirty-seven smaller states are only represented by seven members who take their seats in the court in rotation according to a definite plan.

Now it is not clear how the principle of equality can be deemed violated thereby. This principle has really nothing to do with the constitution of an international court so long as no state is compelled to submit itself to such a tribunal against its will. It would be possible to constitute an international court without basing it on the representation of definite states, and that is very likely to come to pass in the future, when fuller confidence in the international judicature is felt. In the proposed composition of the Prize Court expression is given, undoubtedly, to the actually existing political inequality of states, a matter which, however, has not the least connexion with their legal equality. This political inequality will never disappear from the world, and if in course of time the creation of an international judicature is really intended, the realization of this idea is only possible subject to the existence of political inequality. There is little doubt that when we come to the constituting of the Prize Court certain smaller states will abstain because no permanent representation therein is allotted to them. But it may confidently be expected that the recalcitrant states will give in their adherence in the future, when they begin to see what beneficent results the institution has produced.

Resources

See Also

  • International Human Rights
  • Discrimination
  • Gender Law
  • Women
  • Nationality
  • Civil Liberty
  • Civil Right
  • Legal Right
  • Citizen Freedom
  • Political Liberty
  • Constitutional Right
  • Political Right
  • Freedom of Speech

Further Reading

  • Altman, A., & Wellman, C. H. (2009). A liberal theory of international justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Anderson, E. (1999). What is the point of equality? Ethics, 109(2), 287–337.
  • Appiah, K. A. (2006). Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a world of strangers. New York: W. W. Norton.
  • Armstrong, C. (2013). Natural resources: The demands of equality. Journal of Social Philosophy, 44(4), 331–347.
  • Armstrong, C. (2014). Justice and attachment to natural resources. Journal of Political Philosophy, 22(1), 48–65.
  • Barry, B. (1998). International society from a cosmopolitan perspective. In D. Mapel & T. Nardin (Eds.), International society: Diverse ethical perspectives (pp. 144–163). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Nine, C. (2012). Global justice and territory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Nussbaum, M.C. (1996). Patriotism and cosmopolitanism. In J. Cohen (Ed.), For love of country: Debating the limits of patriotism. Boston: Beacon.
  • Nussbaum, M.C. (2000). Women and human development: The capabilities approach. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
  • Nussbaum, M.C. (2006). Frontiers of justice: disability, nationality, species membership. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.
  • Nussbaum, M.C. (2011). Creating capabilities: The human development approach. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.
  • O’Neill, M. (2008). What should egalitarians believe?. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 36(2), 119–156.
  • O’Neill, O. (1996). Towards justice and virtue. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
  • O’Neill, O. (2001). Transnational economic justice. In O. O’Neill (Ed.), Bounds of justice. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
  • Parfit, D. (2002). Equality or priority?. In M. Clayton & A. Williams (Eds.), The ideal of equality. Basingstoke, U.K.: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Pogge, T. (1989). Realizing Rawls. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Pogge, T. (1994). Cosmopolitanism and sovereignty. In C. Brown (Ed.), Political restructuring in Europe: Ethical perspectives (pp. 89–122). London: Routledge.
  • Pogge, T. (2002). World poverty and human rights: Cosmopolitan responsibilities and reforms. Cambridge, U.K.: Polity Press.
  • Pogge, T. (2007a). Severe poverty as a human rights violation. In T. Pogge (Ed.), Freedom from poverty as a human right: Who owes what to the very poor? New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Pogge, T. (2007b). Cosmopolitanism. In R.E. Goodin, P. Pettit, & T. Pogge (Eds.), A companion to contemporary political philosophy (2d ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Pogge, T. (2007c). Why inequality matters. In D. Held & A. Kaya (Eds.), Global inequality: Patterns and explanations (pp. 132–147). Cambridge, U.K.: Polity Press.
  • Pogge, T. (2010). Politics as usual: What lies behind the pro-poor rhetoric. Cambridge, U.K.: Polity Press.
  • Rawls, J. (1999a). A theory of justice (rev. ed). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Originally published in 1971.
  • Rawls, J. (1999b). The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Ridge, M. (2010). Fairness and non-compliance. In B. Feltham & J. Cottingham (Eds.), Partiality and impartiality: Morality, special relationships, and the wider world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Risse, M. (2005). Do we owe the global poor assistance or rectification? Ethics & International Affairs, 19(1), 10–18.
  • Risse, M. (2006). What to say about the state. Social Theory and Practice, 32(4), 671–698.
  • Risse, M. (2012). On global justice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Sangiovanni, A. (2007). Global justice, reciprocity, and the state. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35(1), 3–39.
  • Scheffler, S. (1982). The rejection of consequentialism: A philosophical investigation of the considerations underlying rival moral conceptions (rev. ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Scheffler, S. (1999). Conceptions of cosmopolitanism. Utilitas, 11(3), 255–276.
  • Scheffler, S. (2002a). Liberalism, nationalism, and egalitarianism. In S. Scheffler (Ed.), Boundaries and allegiances: Problems of justice and responsibility in liberal thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Scheffler, S. (2002b). Relationships and responsibilities. In S. Scheffler (Ed.), Boundaries and allegiances: Problems of justice and responsibility in liberal thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Scheffler, S. (2010). Morality and reasonable partiality. In B. Feltham, & J. Cottingham (Eds.), Partiality and Impartiality: morality, special relationships, and the wider world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Sen, A. (1981). Poverty and famines: An essay on entitlement and deprivation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. London: Allen Lane.
  • Shachar, S. (2009). The birthright lottery: Citizenship and global inequality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Sher, G. (1980). Ancient wrongs and modern rights. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 10(1), 3–17.
  • Shue, H. (1993). Subsistence emissions and luxury emissions. Law and Policy, 15(1), 39–59.
  • Shue, H. (1996). Basic rights: subsistence, affluence, and U.S. foreign policy (2d ed). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Shue, H. (1999). Global environment and international equality. International Affairs, 75(3), 531–545.
  • Shue, H. (2011). Human rights, climate change, and the trillionth ton. In D. Arnold (Ed.), The ethics of global climate change (pp. 292–314). Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
  • Simmons, A. J. (2001). On the territorial rights of states. Philosophical Issues, 11(1), 300–326.
  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 1(3), 229–243.
  • Singer, P. (2002). One world: The ethics of globalization. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • Singer, P. (2009). The life you can save: Acting now to end world poverty. New York: Random House.
  • Steiner, H. (1999). Just taxation and international redistribution. In I. Shapiro, & L. Brilmayer (Eds.), NOMOS XLI: Global justice. New York: New York University Press.
  • Steiner, H. (2005). Territorial justice and global redistribution. In G. Brock & H. Brighouse (Eds.), The political philosophy of cosmopolitanism. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
  • Stiglitz, J. (2006). Making globalization work. New York: Norton.
  • Stiglitz, J., & Charlton, A. (2006). Fair trade for all: How trade can promote development. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Stilz, A. (2009). Why do states have territorial rights? International Theory, 1(2), 185–213.
  • Stilz, A. (2011). Nations, states, and territory. Ethics, 121(3), 572–601.
  • Tamir, Y. (1993). Liberal nationalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Tan, K. (2011). Justice, institutions, and luck: The site, ground, and scope of equality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Tesón, F. R., & Klick, J. (2012). Global justice and trade. In C. Carmody, F. J. Garcia, & J. Linarelli (Eds.), Global justice and international economic law: Opportunities and prospects (pp. 217–260). Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
  • Unger, P. (1996). Living high and letting die: Our illusion of innocence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • United Nations Development Programme (UNDP) (2014). Human development report 2014, sustaining human progress: Reducing vulnerabilities and building resilience. Retrieved from https://hdr.undp.org/sites/default/files/hdr14-report-en-1.pdf.
  • Vanderheiden, S. (2008). Atmospheric justice: A political theory of climate change. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Waldron, J. (1992). Superseding historic injustice. Ethics, 103(1), 4–28.
  • Waltz, K. (1959). Man, the state, and war: A theoretical analysis. New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Waltz, K. (1978). Theory of international politics. Boston: McGraw-Hill.
  • Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice: A defense of pluralism and equality. New York: Basic Books.
  • Wenar, L. (2008). Property rights and the resource curse. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 36(1), 2–32.
  • Weston, P. (1982). The empty idea of equality. Harvard Law Review, 95(3), 537–596.
  • Wolf, M. (2005). Why globalization works. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • Ypi, L. (2012). Global justice and avant-garde political agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ypi, L., Goodin, R. E., & Barry, C. (2009). Associative duties, global justice, and colonies. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(2), 103–135.
  • Comments

    Leave a Reply

    Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *